友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!
introduction to the metaphysic of morals-第5部分
快捷操作: 按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页 按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页 按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部! 如果本书没有阅读完,想下次继续接着阅读,可使用上方 "收藏到我的浏览器" 功能 和 "加入书签" 功能!
feeling。 We do not; however; take the moral feelings or sentiments
into account in considering the practical laws of reason。 For they
do not form the foundation or principle of practical laws of reason;
but only the subjective effects that arise in the mind on the occasion
of our voluntary activity being determined by these laws。 And while
they neither add to nor take from the objective validity or
influence of the moral laws in the judgement of reason; such
sentiments may vary according to the differences of the individuals
who experience them。
The following conceptions are common to jurisprudence and ethics
as the two main divisions of the metaphysic of morals。
Obligation is the necessity of a free action when viewed in relation
to a categorical imperative of reason。 An imperative is a practical
rule by which an action; otherwise contingent in itself; is made
necessary。 It is distinguished from a practical law in that such a
law; while likewise representing the action as necessary; does not
consider whether it is internally necessary as involved in the
nature of the agent… say as a holy being… or is contingent to him;
as in the case of man as we find him; for where the first condition
holds good; there is in fact no imperative。 Hence an imperative is a
rule which not only represents but makes a subjectively contingent
action necessary; and it; accordingly; represents the subject as being
(morally) necessitated to act in accordance with this rule。 A
categorical or unconditional imperative is one which does not
represent the action in any way immediately through the conception
of an end that is to be attained by it; but it presents the action
to the mind as objectively necessary by the mere representation of its
form as an action; and thus makes it necessary。 Such imperatives
cannot be put forward by any other practical science than that which
prescribes obligations; and it is only the science of morals that does
this。 All other imperatives are technical; and they are altogether
conditional。 The ground of the possibility of categorical
imperatives lies in the fact that they refer to no determination of
the activity of the will by which a purpose might be assigned to it;
but solely to its freedom。
Every action is allowed (licitum) which is not contrary to
obligation; and this freedom not being limited by an opposing
imperative; constitutes a moral right as a warrant or title of
action (facultas moralis)。 From this it is at once evident what
actions are disallowed or illicit (illicita)。
Duty is the designation of any action to which anyone is bound by an
obligation。 It is therefore the subject…matter of all obligation。 Duty
as regards the action concerned may be one and the same; and yet we
may be bound to it in various ways。
The categorical imperative; as expressing an obligation in respect
to certain actions; is a morally practical law。 But because obligation
involves not merely practical necessity expressed in a law as such;
but also actual necessitation; the categorical imperative is a law
either of command or prohibition; according as the doing or not
doing of an action is represented as a duty。 An action which is
neither commanded nor forbidden is merely allowed; because there is no
law restricting freedom; nor any duty in respect of it。 Such an action
is said to be morally indifferent (indifferens; adiaphoron; res
merae facultatis)。 It may be asked whether there are such morally
indifferent actions; and if there are; whether in addition to the
preceptive and prohibitive law (lex praeceptiva et prohibitiva; lex
mandati et vetiti); there is also required a permissive law (lex
permissiva); in order that one may be free in such relations to act;
or to forbear from acting; at his pleasure? If it were so; the moral
right in question would not; in all cases; refer to actions that are
indifferent in themselves (adiaphora); for no special law would be
required to establish such a right; considered according to moral
laws。
An action is called an act… or moral deed… in so far as it is
subject to laws of obligation; and consequently in so far as the
subject of it is regarded with reference to the freedom of his
choice in the exercise of his will。 The agent… as the actor or doer of
the deed… is regarded as; through the act; the author of its effect;
and this effect; along with the action itself; may be imputed to
him; if be previously knew the law in virtue of which an obligation
rested upon him。
A person is a subject who is capable of having his actions imputed
to him。 Moral personality is; therefore; nothing but the freedom of
a rational being under moral laws; and it is to be distinguished
from psychological freedom as the mere faculty by which we become
conscious of ourselves in different states of the identity of our
existence。 Hence it follows that a person is properly subject to no
other laws than those he lays down for himself; either alone or in
conjunction with others。
A thing is what is incapable of being the subject of imputation。
Every object of the free activity of the will; which is itself void of
freedom; is therefore called a thing (res corporealis)。
Right or wrong applies; as a general quality; to an act (rectum
aut minus rectum); in so far as it is in accordance with duty or
contrary to duty (factum licitum aut illicitum); no matter what may be
the subject or origin of the duty itself。 An act that is contrary to
duty is called a transgression (reatus)。
An unintentional transgression of a duty; which is; nevertheless;
imputable to a person; is called a mere fault (culpa)。 An
intentional transgression… that is; an act accompanied with the
consciousness that it is a transgression… constitutes a crime (dolus)。
Whatever is juridically in accordance with external laws is said
to be just (jus; instum); and whatever is not juridically in
accordance with external laws is unjust (unjustum)。
A collision of duties or obligations (collisio officiorum s。
obligationum) would be the result of such a relation between them that
the one would annul the other; in whole or in part。 Duty and
obligation; however; are conceptions which express the objective
practical necessity of certain actions; and two opposite rules
cannot be objective and necessary at the same time; for if it is a
duty to act according to one of them; it is not only no duty to act
according to an opposite rule; but to do so would even be contrary
to duty。 Hence a collision of duties and obligations is entirely
inconceivable (obligationes non colliduntur)。 There may; however; be
two grounds of obligation (rationes obligandi); connected with an
individual under a rule prescribed for himself; and yet neither the
one nor the other may be sufficient to constitute an actual obligation
(rationes obligandi non obligantes); and in that case the one of
them is not a duty。 If two such grounds of obligation are actually
in collision with each other; practical philosophy does not say that
the stronger obligation is to keep the upper hand (fortior obligatio
vincit); but that the stronger ground of obligation is to maintain its
place (fortior obligandi ratio vincit)。
Obligatory Laws for which an external legislation is possible are
called generally external laws。 Those external laws; the
obligatoriness of which can be recognised by reason a priori even
without an external legislation; are called natural laws。 Those
laws; again; which are not obligatory without actual external
legislation; are called positive laws。 An external legislation;
containing pure natural laws; is therefore conceivable; but in that
case a previous natural law must be presupposed to establish the
authority of the lawgiver by the right to subject others to obligation
through his own act of will。
The principle which makes a certain action a duty is a practical
law。 The rule of the agent or actor; which he forms as a principle for
himself on subjective grounds; is called his maxim。 Hence; even when
the law is one and invariable; the maxims of the agent may yet be very
different。
The categorical imperative only expresses generally what constitutes
obligation。 It may be rendered by the following formula: 〃Act
according to a maxim which can be adopted at the same time as a
universal law。〃 Actions must therefore be considered; in the first
place; according to their subjective principle; but whether this
principle is also valid objectively can only be known by the criterion
of the categorical imperative。 For reason brings the principle or
maxim of any action to the test; by calling upon the agent to think of
himself in connection with it as at the same time laying down a
universal law; and to consider whether his action is so qualified as
to be fit for entering into such a universal legislation。
The simplicity of this law; in comparison with the great and
manifold consequences which ma
快捷操作: 按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页 按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页 按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!