友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!
introduction to the metaphysic of morals-第3部分
快捷操作: 按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页 按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页 按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部! 如果本书没有阅读完,想下次继续接着阅读,可使用上方 "收藏到我的浏览器" 功能 和 "加入书签" 功能!
to be deduced by the metaphysical science from principles a priori。
Thus Newton accepted the principle of the equality of action and
reaction as established by experience; and yet he extended it as a
universal law over the whole of material nature。 The chemists go
even farther; grounding their most general laws regarding the
combination and decomposition of the materials of bodies wholly upon
experience; and yet they trust so completely to the universality and
necessity of those laws that they have no anxiety as to any error
being found in propositions founded upon experiments conducted in
accordance with them。
But it is otherwise with moral laws。 These; in contradistinction
to natural laws; are only valid as laws; in so far as they can be
rationally established a priori and comprehended as necessary。 In
fact; conceptions and judgements regarding ourselves and our conduct
have no moral significance; if they contain only what may be learned
from experience; and when any one is; so to speak; misled into
making a moral principle out of anything derived from this latter
source; he is already in danger of falling into the coarsest and
most fatal errors。
If the philosophy of morals were nothing more than a theory of
happiness (eudaemonism); it would be absurd to search after principles
a priori as a foundation for it。 For however plausible it may sound to
say that reason; even prior to experience; can comprehend by what
means we may attain to a lasting enjoyment of the real pleasures of
life; yet all that is taught on this subject a priori is either
tautological; or is assumed wholly without foundation。 It is only
experience that can show what will bring us enjoyment。 The natural
impulses directed towards nourishment; the sexual instinct; or the
tendency to rest and motion; as well as the higher desires of
honour; the acquisition of knowledge; and such like; as developed with
our natural capacities; are alone capable of showing in what those
enjoyments are to be found。 And; further; the knowledge thus
acquired is available for each individual merely in his own way; and
it is only thus he can learn the means by which be has to seek those
enjoyments。 All specious rationalizing a priori; in this connection;
is nothing at bottom but carrying facts of experience up to
generalizations by induction (secundum principia generalia non
universalia); and the generality thus attained is still so limited
that numberless exceptions must be allowed to every individual in
order that he may adapt the choice of his mode of life to his own
Particular inclinations and his capacity for pleasure。 And; after all;
the individual has really to acquire his prudence at the cost of his
own suffering or that of his neighbors the form
But it is quite otherwise with the principles of morality。 They
lay down commands for every one without regard to his particular
inclinations; and merely because and so far as he is free; and has a
practical reason。 Instruction in the laws of morality is not drawn
from observation of oneself or of our animal nature; nor from
perception of the course of the world in regard to what happens; or
how men act。* But reason commands how we ought to act; even although
no example of such action were to be found; nor does reason give any
regard to the advantage which may accrue to us by so acting; and which
experience could alone actually show。 For; although reason allows us
to seek what is for our advantage in every possible way; and although;
founding upon the evidence of experience; it may further promise
that greater advantages will probably follow on the average from the
observance of her commands than from their transgression; especially
if prudence guides the conduct; yet the authority of her precepts as
commands does not rest on such considerations。 They are used by reason
only as counsels; and by way of a counterpoise against seductions to
an opposite course; when adjusting beforehand the equilibrium of a
partial balance in the sphere of practical judgement; in order thereby
to secure the decision of this judgement; according to the due
weight of the a priori principles of a pure practical reason。
*This holds notwithstanding the fact that the term morals;〃 in Latin
mores; and in German sitten; signifies originally only manners or mode
of life。
Metaphysics designates any system of knowledge a priori that
consists of pure conceptions。 Accordingly; a practical philosophy
not having nature; but the freedom of the will for its object; will
presuppose and require a metaphysic of morals。 It is even a duty to
have such a metaphysic; and every man does; indeed; possess it in
himself; although commonly but in an obscure way。 For how could any
one believe that he has a source of universal law in himself;
without principles a priori? And just as in a metaphysics of nature
there must be principles regulating the application of the universal
supreme principles of nature to objects of experience; so there cannot
but be such principles in the metaphysic of morals; and we will
often have to deal objectively with the particular nature of man as
known only by experience; in order to show in it the consequences of
these universal moral principles。 But this mode of dealing with
these principles in their particular applications will in no way
detract from their rational purity; or throw doubt on their a priori
origin。 In other words; this amounts to saying that a metaphysic of
morals cannot be founded on anthropology as the empirical science of
man; but may be applied to it。
The counterpart of a metaphysic of morals; and the other member of
the division of practical philosophy; would be a moral anthropology;
as the empirical science of the moral nature of man。 This science
would contain only the subjective conditions that hinder or favor
the realization in practice of the universal moral laws in human
nature; with the means of propagating; spreading; and strengthening
the moral principles… as by the education of the young and the
instruction of the people… and all other such doctrines and precepts
founded upon experience and indispensable in themselves; although they
must neither precede the metaphysical investigation of the
principles of reason; nor be mixed up with it。 For; by doing so; there
would be a great danger of laying down false; or at least very
flexible moral laws; which would hold forth as unattainable what is
not attached only because the law has not been comprehended and
presented in its purity; in which also its strength consists。 Or;
otherwise; spurious and mixed motives might be adopted instead of what
is dutiful and good in itself; and these would furnish no certain
moral principles either for the guidance of the judgement or for the
discipline of the heart in the practice of duty。 It is only by pure
reason; therefore; that duty can and must be prescribed。
The higher division of philosophy; under which the division just
mentioned stands; is into theoretical philosophy and practical
philosophy。 Practical philosophy is just moral philosophy in its
widest sense; as has been explained elsewhere。* All that is
practicable and possible; according to natural laws; is the special
subject of the activity of art; and its precepts and rules entirely
depend on the theory of nature。 It is only what is practicable
according to laws of freedom that can have principles independent of
theory; for there is no theory in relation to what passes beyond the
determinations of nature。 Philosophy therefore cannot embrace under
its practical division a technical theory; but only a morally
practical doctrine。 But if the dexterity of the will in acting
according to laws of freedom; in contradistinction to nature; were
to be also called an art; it would necessarily indicate an art which
would make a system of freedom possible like the system of nature。
This would truly be a Divine art; if we were in a position by means of
it to realize completely what reason prescribes to us; and to put
the idea into practice。
*In the Critique of Judgement (1790)。
III。 THE DIVISION OF A METAPHYSIC OF MORALS。
All legislation; whether relating to internal or external action;
and whether prescribed a priori by mere reason or laid down by the
will of another; involves two elements: First; a law which
represents the action that ought to happen as necessary objectively;
thus making the action a duty; second; a motive which connects the
principle determining the will to this action with the mental
representation of the law subjectively; so that the law makes duty the
motive of the action。 By the first element; the action is
represented as a duty; in accordance with the mere theoretical
knowledge of the possibility of determining the activity of the will
by practical rules。 By the second element; the obligation so to act is
connected in the subject
快捷操作: 按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页 按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页 按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!